Results for 'Zachary J. Williams'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  30
    The conceptual foundation of the propensity interpretation of fitness.Zachary J. Mayne - 2024 - Synthese 203 (10).
    The propensity interpretation of fitness (PIF) holds that evolutionary fitness is an objectively probabilistic causal disposition (i.e., a propensity) toward reproductive success. I characterize this as the conceptual foundation of the PIF. Reproductive propensities are meant to explain trends in actual reproductive outcomes. In this paper, I analyze the minimal theoretical and ontological commitments that must accompany the explanatory power afforded by the PIF’s foundation. I discuss three senses in which these commitments are less burdensome than has typically been recognized: (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  8
    Causal Structure Learning in Continuous Systems.Zachary J. Davis, Neil R. Bramley & Bob Rehder - 2020 - Frontiers in Psychology 11.
    Real causal systems are complicated. Despite this, causal learning research has traditionally emphasized how causal relations can be induced on the basis of idealized events, i.e. those that have been mapped to binary variables and abstracted from time. For example, participants may be asked to assess the efficacy of a headache-relief pill on the basis of multiple patients who take the pill (or not) and find their headache relieved (or not). In contrast, the current study examines learning via interactions with (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  3.  17
    The conceptual foundation of the propensity interpretation of fitness.Zachary J. Mayne - 2023 - Synthese 203 (1):1-23.
    The propensity interpretation of fitness (PIF) holds that evolutionary fitness is an objectively probabilistic causal disposition (i.e., a propensity) toward reproductive success. I characterize this as the conceptual foundation of the PIF. Reproductive propensities are meant to explain trends in actual reproductive outcomes. In this paper, I analyze the minimal theoretical and ontological commitments that must accompany the explanatory power afforded by the PIF’s foundation. I discuss three senses in which these commitments are less burdensome than has typically been recognized: (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  30
    A Process Model of Causal Reasoning.Zachary J. Davis & Bob Rehder - 2020 - Cognitive Science 44 (5):e12839.
    How do we make causal judgments? Many studies have demonstrated that people are capable causal reasoners, achieving success on tasks from reasoning to categorization to interventions. However, less is known about the mental processes used to achieve such sophisticated judgments. We propose a new process model—the mutation sampler—that models causal judgments as based on a sample of possible states of the causal system generated using the Metropolis–Hastings sampling algorithm. Across a diverse array of tasks and conditions encompassing over 1,700 participants, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  5.  77
    Evil and a Worthwhile Life.Zachary J. Goldberg - 2017 - In Reflections on Ethics and Responsibility: Essays in Honor of Peter A. French. Springer. pp. 145-163.
    The concept of evil plays a central role in many of Peter French’s publications. He defines evil as “a human action that jeopardizes another person’s (or group’s) aspirations to live a worthwhile life (or lives) by the willful infliction of undeserved harm on that person(s)” (French 2011, 61, 95). Inspired by Harry Frankfurt’s work on the importance of what we care about, French argues that “the life a person leads is worthwhile if what he or she really gives a damn (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  6.  23
    The Ambivalence of Husserl’s Early Logic: Between Austrian Semanticism and German Idealism.Zachary J. Joachim - 2024 - Husserl Studies 40 (1):45-65.
    Prolegomena to Pure Logic (1900) is the definitive statement of Husserl’s early logic. But what does it say that logic is? I argue that Husserl in the Prolegomena thinks logic is its own discipline, namely the “doctrine of science” (Wissenschaftslehre), but has two conflicting ideas of what that is. One idea—expressed by the book’s general argument, and which I call Husserl’s Austrian Semanticism about logic—is that the Wissenschaftslehre is the positive science explaining what science is (which turns out just to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  16
    Segregation and belief polarization as boundary conditions for when fusion leads to self-sacrifice.Zachary J. Melton & Matt Motyl - 2018 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 41.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  57
    A Relational Approach to Evil Action: Vulnerability and its Exploitation.Zachary J. Goldberg - 2019 - Journal of Value Inquiry 53 (1):33-53.
    In this article I seek a more complete understanding of evil action. To this end, in the first half of the article I assess the conceptual strengths and weaknesses of the most compelling theories of evil action found in the contemporary philosophical literature. I conclude that the theories that fall under the category I call ‘‘Nuanced Harm Accounts’’ successfully identify the necessary and sufficient conditions of the concept. However, necessary and sufficient conditions are not coextensive with significant features, and Nuanced (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  9. Evolutionary Game Theory and the Origins of Fairness Norms.Zachary J. Ernst - 2002 - Dissertation, The University of Wisconsin - Madison
    In numerous studies, experimental economists have documented the fact that people tend to propose that divisible goods be divided equally. It has often been proposed, most notably by the sociobiologists, that this tendency may have a biological basis, and might be the product of evolution and natural selection. ;My dissertation addresses methodological and philosophical problems that arise in the course of establishing this naturalistic claim. Specifically, the focus of this dissertation is on the project of using evolutionary game theory to (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10. Maimonides and the Visual Image after Kant and Cohen.Zachary J. Braiterman - 2012 - Journal of Jewish Thought and Philosophy 20 (2):217-230.
    In this paper, I attempt to consider Jewish philosophy in opposition to the anti-ocularcentrism that defined the German Jewish philosophical tradition after Kant, namely the idea that Judaism—or at least its philosophical expression in Maimonidean philosophy—is aniconic and cognitively abstract. I do so by attempting to rethink the epistemic-veridical place of the imagination and visual experience in the Guide of the Perplexed . Once the imagination has been disciplined by reason, is there any cognitive status to an image or sound (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11. Can Kant’s Theory of Radical Evil Be Saved?Zachary J. Goldberg - 2017 - Kantian Review 22 (3):395-419.
    In this article, I assess three contemporary criticisms levelled at Kant’s theory of evil in order to evaluate whether his theory can be saved. Critics argue that Kant does not adequately distinguish between evil and mundane wrongdoing, making his use of the term ‘evil’ emotional hyperbole; by defining evil as the subordination of the moral law to self-love his analysis is seemingly overly simplistic and empirically false; and by focusing solely on the moral character of the perpetrator of evil, Kant’s (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  12.  31
    Evil, "Evil", and Taking Responsibility.Zachary J. Goldberg - 2016 - In Birgit Recki (ed.), Wozu ist das Böse gut? Mentis.
    This essay will address the question for what good or purpose is evil. First, an examination of the use-mention distinction between evil and “evil” produces two distinct questions: what good is the presence of evil in the world, and what good is the concept of evil as part of our ethical vocabulary describing human interaction. By severing all logically necessary connections between evil and greater goods, we discover that the answer to the first question—what good is evil in the world—is (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  13.  11
    Changes in Personality, Mood, and Behavior with TMS and ECT: Current Knowledge and Challenges.Zachary J. Verne & Jeffrey S. Zabinski - 2023 - American Journal of Bioethics Neuroscience 14 (3):325-327.
    Zuk et al. (2023) explore personality, mood, and behavioral (PMB) changes in DBS and aDBS, though have not invoked what is known about the similarities and differences for other available brain sti...
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  15
    Von hügel's 'sense of the infinite'.F. S. C. J. William Beatie - 1975 - Heythrop Journal 16 (2):149–173.
  15. The Inevitability of Evil and Moral Tragedy.Zachary J. Goldberg - 2016 - In Claudio V. Zanini & Lima Bhuiyan (eds.), This Thing of Darkness: Shedding Light on Evil. Interdisciplinary Press. pp. 47-58.
    Although Greek virtue theory, Kantian ethics, and utilitarianism contend that evil and moral tragedy can be avoided, my paper will argue that our recognition of their inevitability provides the only means toward taking full moral responsibility for one’s agency. It is especially tragic to observe that wrongdoing is often inescapable. An agent may have overriding moral reasons to pursue one course of action over another, and yet in making the morally best choice the individual nevertheless transgresses a moral value. My (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  11
    Evil Matters: A Philosophical Inquiry.Zachary J. Goldberg - 2021 - New York: Routledge.
    This book explores the nature, normativity, and aftermath of evil action. It combines philosophical conceptual analysis with empirical studies in psychology and discussions of historical events to provide an innovative analysis of evil action.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  30
    Moral Innocence as Illusion and Inability.Zachary J. Goldberg - 2015 - Philosophia 43 (2):355-366.
    The concept of moral innocence is frequently referenced in popular culture, ordinary language, literature, religious doctrine, and psychology. The morally innocent are often thought to be morally pure, incapable of wrongdoing, ignorant of morality, resistant to sin, or even saintly. In spite of, or perhaps because of this frequency of use the characterization of moral innocence continues to have varying connotations. As a result, the concept is often used without sufficient heed given to some of its most salient attributes, especially (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  59
    Van Inwagen’s Two Failed Arguments for the Belief in Freedom.Zachary J. Goldberg - 2010 - Southwest Philosophy Review 26 (1):43-50.
    In chapter 6 of An Essay on Free Will Peter van Inwagen presents an influential argument that we are justified in believing we are free. He does so by claiming that the determinist’s objection to the argument for the belief in freedom fails in the exact same way that the skeptic’s argument fails to prove that none of our empirical beliefs are justified. I show that this strategy to defend the belief in freedom fails due to a disanalogy. The failure (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  43
    Was ist eine böse Handlung?Zachary J. Goldberg - 2019 - Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie 66 (6):764-787.
    What is the nature of evil action? My thesis is that perpetrators and victims of evil inhabit an asymmetrical relation of power; the strength of the more powerful party lies in its ability to exploit the other’s fundamental vulnerability, and the weaker party is vulnerable precisely insofar as it is directly dependent on the more powerful party for the satisfaction of its fundamental needs. The fundamental vulnerabilities that are exploited correspond to features essential to our humanity (ontological), moral personhood (personal), (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  37
    Moral Innocence as the Negative Counterpart to Moral Maturity.Zachary J. Goldberg - 2016 - In Elizabeth S. Dodd Carl E. Findley (ed.), Innocence Uncovered: Literary and Theological Perspectives. Routledge. pp. 167-182.
    Establishing a precise definition of moral innocence is a difficult task. Ordinarily philosophers explore the necessary and sufficient conditions of a term or concept in order to determine its meaning. Doing so with “moral innocence” proves difficult because the concept is mutable. The term is used in varying contexts to refer to ignorance, naiveté, sexual inexperience, legal and moral culpability, noncombatants in war, and moral purity. For our present purposes, we can exclude the contexts of law and war because they (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  31
    Reflections on Ethics and Responsibility: Essays in Honor of Peter A. French.Zachary J. Goldberg (ed.) - 2017 - Cham: Springer.
    The original essays in this book address the influential writings of Peter A. French on the nature of responsibility, ethics, and moral practices. French’s contributions to a wide spectrum of philosophical discussions have made him a dominant figure in the fields of normative ethics, meta-ethics, applied ethics, as well as legal and political philosophy. Many of French’s deepest insights come from identifying and exploring the scope and nature of moral responsibility and human agency as they appear in actual events, real (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  18
    The Routledge International Handbook of Perpetrator Studies.Suzanne C. Knittel & Zachary J. Goldberg (eds.) - 2019
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  29
    The cosmological and ontological arguments: How saint Thomas solved the Kantian problem: J. William Forgie.J. William Forgie - 1995 - Religious Studies 31 (1):89-100.
    Let us call the Dependency Theses the view, first stated by Kant, that certain versions of the cosmological argument depend on the ontological argument. At least two different reasons have been given for the supposed dependence. Given the DT, some of Aquinas' views about God's essence, and about our knowledge of God's existence, can seem, at least at first, to be inconsistent. I consider two different ways of defending Aquinas against this suspicion of inconsistency. On the first defence, based on (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  24.  17
    Uninformed Origins: Should We Be Advising Parents on the Source of Medicines and Therapies?Tara E. Ness, Zachary J. Tabb, Janet Malek & Frank X. Placencia - 2023 - Health Care Analysis 31 (3):186-195.
    Respecting patient autonomy through the process of soliciting informed consent is a cornerstone of clinical ethics. In pediatrics, until a child becomes an adult or legally emancipated, that ethical tenet takes the form of respect for parental decision-making authority. In instances of respecting religious beliefs, doing so is not always apparent and sometimes the challenge lies not only in the healthcare provider’s familiarity of religious restrictions but also their knowledge of medical interventions themselves which might conflict with those restrictions. We (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  93
    From Enlightenment to Receptivity: Rethinking Our Values. [REVIEW]Zachary J. Goldberg - 2014 - Philosophical Quarterly 64 (255):347-349.
  26.  35
    Group Agency: The Possibility, Design, and Status of Corporate Agents. [REVIEW]Zachary J. Goldberg - 2015 - Philosophical Quarterly 65 (259):280-282.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27. Kierkegaard. [REVIEW]Zachary J. Goldberg - 2011 - Philosophical Forum 42 (3):321-321.
    This is a review of Terence Irwin's chapter on Kierkegaard in his The Development of Ethics.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  65
    Kant and Frege: Existence as a Second-Level Property.J. William Forgie - 2000 - Kant Studien 91 (2):165-177.
  29.  85
    Counterfactual Triviality: A Lewis‐Impossibility Argument for Counterfactuals.J. Robert & G. Williams - 2012 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 85 (3):648-670.
    I formulate a counterfactual version of the notorious ‘Ramsey Test’. Whereas the Ramsey Test for indicative conditionals links credence in indicatives to conditional credences, the counterfactual version links credence in counterfactuals to expected conditional chance. I outline two forms: a Ramsey Identity on which the probability of the conditional should be identical to the corresponding conditional probability/expectation of chance; and a Ramsey Bound on which credence in the conditional should never exceed the latter. Even in the weaker, bound, form, the (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  30.  20
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy: The Concept of Evil.Peter A. French & Zachary J. Goldberg - 2012 - Wiley-Blackwell.
    __The Concept of Evil__ is dedicated to the analysis of the concept of evil. The term "evil" is used widely in ordinary language and yet philosophers have disagreed on what, if anything, distinguishes an evil act from a wrong act or an evil person from a bad one. Is "evil" a distinct and important moral category? Which agents and acts can and should be classified as "evil"? In which areas of practice does evil arise? These questions indicate three essential categories (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  42
    Existence Assertions and the Ontological Argument.J. William Forgie - 1974 - Mind 83:260.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  32.  63
    The Cosmological and Ontological Arguments: How Saint Thomas Solved the Kantian Problem.J. William Forgie - 1995 - Religious Studies 31 (1):89 - 100.
    Let us call the Dependency Theses (DT) the view, first stated by Kant, that certain versions of the cosmological argument depend on the ontological argument. At least two different reasons have been given for the supposed dependence. Given the DT, some of Aquinas' views about God's essence, and about our knowledge of God's existence, can seem, at least at first, to be inconsistent. I consider two different ways of defending Aquinas against this suspicion of inconsistency. On the first defence, based (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  33.  39
    How is the question ‘Is Existence a Predicate?’ relevant to the ontological argument?J. William Forgie - 2008 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 64 (3):117-133.
    It is often said that the ontological argument fails because it wrongly treats existence as a first-level property or predicate. This has proved a controversial claim, and efforts to evaluate it are complicated by the fact that the words ‘existence is not a property/predicate’ have been used by philosophers to make at least three different negative claims: (a) one about a first-level phenomenon possessed by objects like horses, stones, you and me; (b) another about the logical form of assertions of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  34.  85
    Kant and the Question "Is Existence a Predicate?".J. William Forgie - 1975 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 5 (4):563 - 582.
    Kant gave a two-fold answer to the question, ‘Is existence a predicate?’. His view that existence is not a first-level predicate, i.e., a predicate of objects like horses, stones, and you and me, is widely known. What is not so well-known, however, is his claim that existence is a second-level predicate, a predicate of concepts or of a collection of predicates. In this paper I hope to show why his arguments for both claims are unsuccessful.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  35.  91
    Kant and Existence: Critique of Pure Reason A 600/b 628.J. William Forgie - 2008 - Kant Studien 99 (1):1-12.
    By whatever and by however many predicates we may think a thing – even if we completely determine it – we do not make the least addition to the thing when we further declare that this thing is. Otherwise, it would not be exactly the same thing that exists, but something more than we had thought in the concept; and we could not, therefore, say that the exact object of my concept exists.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  36. How is the question 'is existence a predicate?' Relevant to the ontological argument?J. William Forgie - 2008 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 64 (3):117 - 133.
    It is often said that the ontological argument fails because it wrongly treats existence as a first-level property or predicate. This has proved a controversial claim, and efforts to evaluate it are complicated by the fact that the words ‘existence is not a property/predicate’ have been used by philosophers to make at least three different negative claims: (a) one about a first-level phenomenon possessed by objects like horses, stones, you and me; (b) another about the logical form of assertions of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  37. Frege's objection to the ontological argument.J. William Forgie - 1972 - Noûs 6 (3):251-265.
    Frege argued that 1) in making existence assertions we ascribe (or deny) the second-Level property, 'not being empty', To a first-Level concept. He inferred from this that 2) existence is a second-Level property, The property 'not being empty'. He therefore rejected the ontological proof of the existence of God because, He claimed, It depends on the assumption that existence is a first-Level, And not a second-Level, Property. In this paper it is argued, First, That frege is unsuccessful in his attempt (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  38.  26
    Hyper–Kantianism in Recent Discussions of Mystical Experience.J. William Forgie - 1985 - Religious Studies 21 (2):205 - 218.
    Much work on mystical experience has taken for granted a certain view about the relation between experience and its interpretation. This ‘traditional view’ has received perhaps its most explicit statement in Stace's Mysticism and Philosophy . It is a view which is attractive to proponents of the doctrine of unanimity, the doctrine that at the phenomenological level all mystical experiences are basically similar. Recently, however, in a growing body of literature, the traditional view has come under heavy fire. Its critics (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  39.  72
    Kant on the relation between the cosmological and ontological arguments.J. William Forgie - 1993 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 34 (1):1 - 12.
  40.  55
    The caterus objection.J. William Forgie - 1990 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 28 (2):81 - 104.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  41.  12
    Science, media and society: the framing of bioethical debates around embyonic stem cell research between 2000 and 2005.J. Kitzinger, C. Williams & L. Henderson - unknown
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  33
    Existence and Properties.J. William Forgie - 1977 - New Scholasticism 51 (1):102-116.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  83
    Is the Cartesian Ontological Argument Defensible?J. William Forgie - 1976 - New Scholasticism 50 (1):108-121.
  44.  40
    Mystical Experience and the Argument from Agreement.J. William Forgie - 1985 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 17 (3):97 - 113.
  45.  29
    Pike's Mystic Union and the Possibility of Theistic Experience.J. William Forgie - 1994 - Religious Studies 30 (2):231 - 242.
    In his long-awaited Mystic Union , Nelson Pike offers a phenomenology of mysticism. His account is based on the reports and descriptions of third parties, not on his own, first-person experience. So he calls his enterprise ‘phenomenography’, an attempt to describe the experiential content of conscious states by way of reports of them. Pike finds in the Christian mystical tradition three different kinds of experiences of mystic union, the ‘prayer of quiet’, the ‘prayer of union’ and ‘rapture’. These experiences differ (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  36
    The Alleged Dependency of the Cosmological Argument on the Ontological.J. William Forgie - 2003 - Faith and Philosophy 20 (3):364-370.
  47.  37
    Thestic Experience and the Doctrine Of Unanimity.J. William Forgie - 1984 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 15 (1/2):13 - 30.
  48. The modal ontological argument and the necessary a posteriori.J. William Forgie - 1991 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 29 (3):129 - 141.
  49.  57
    The principle of credulity and the evidential value of religious experience.J. William Forgie - 1986 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 19 (3):145 - 159.
  50.  66
    Wittgenstein on Naming and Ostensive Definition.J. William Forgie - 1976 - International Studies in Philosophy 8:13-26.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 1000